Neoliberal Administrative State, Digitalization and Pandemic
Sergei V. Korolev
a
and Irina S. Lyalina
b
Institute of State and Law of the Russian Academy of Sciences, Moscow, Russia
Keywords: Globalization, Neoliberalism, Information, Digitalization, COVID-19, Administrative State, Neoliberal
Administrative Empire.
Abstract: The article examines theoretical approaches to understanding the state - from the classical definition given by
G. Jellinek, to the public-private imposition of Maurice Oriou, its transformation under the influence of a
pandemic from a constitutional state with a liberal-democratic regime into a neoliberal administrative state.
The role of digitalization as an internal process of optimization of an administrative state and an external
process of optimization of a welfare state, digitalization trends characterizing the relationship between the
administrative apparatus of the state and its citizens, as well as its importance in overcoming the current crisis
of the state are investigated. The dichotomy "objective-subjective" in digitalization processes and the context
of a pandemic is considered. The impact of the COVID-19 pandemic on the digital status of a person and the
challenges and threats posed by the digitalization of a covid database from a neoliberal administrative state
are discussed.
1 INTRODUCTION
We live in the era of transformation, fragmentation
and even diffusion of what Karl Schmitt called
"political theology"(Schmitt, 2000). It is based on the
concept, and from the point of view of K. Schmitt's
ideological myth that state power is "neutral power"
(Schmitt, 2000). In other words, political theology is
the product of a triumphant legal positivism,
according to which - in the words of Georg Jellinek -
the state limits itself to law (Jellinek, 1929). As a
result, continuing the logic of Jellinek, Hans Kelsen
was able to complete the concept of neutral power in
his theory of "pure law". According to this theory, the
state is, first of all, a legal structure, that is, law is
primary, and the state is derived from it (Kelsen,
1992).
The concept of "neutral power" has long been a
subject of debate among constitutionalists. Karl
Schmitt, in contrast to it, developed his own doctrine
called "decisionism" (Schmitt, 2000) in fact, we are
talking about a paradigm change in the classical ideas
about the state, law, social interaction, about the
person himself/herself. Undoubtedly, this process did
not begin yesterday: especially the representatives of
a
https://orcid.org/0000-0001-9305-0274
b
https://orcid.org/0000-0002-2060-4851
Scandinavian legal realism did a lot to make a hole in
the seemingly impregnable fortress of legal
positivism (Lyles, 2009).
Therefore, in his work "The Unscientific Nature
of Legal Science" Anders Wilhelm Lundstedt, using
the term "state" as an example, actually accuses
classical jurisprudence of being the secret heir of
medieval realism. Lundstedt poses the following
question: what is the meaning of the phrase about
state neutrality in the struggle between workers and
employers? He himself answers: none, since it is
impossible to present the state as something third.
After all, if we “eliminate” workers and employers,
then what will then be left of the “state”? Only desert
and "dead existence". The state, according to
Lundstedt, is only a designation of a social
organization in its entirety and nothing more
(Lundstedt, 1932).
2 STUDY METHODS
This paper uses a logical, historical, sociological and
systematic method. The latter is a legal way of
understanding intersectoral relationships within the
392
Korolev, S. and Lyalina, I.
Neoliberal Administrative State, Digitalization and Pandemic.
DOI: 10.5220/0011121200003439
In Proceedings of the 2nd International Scientific and Practical Conference "COVID-19: Implementation of the Sustainable Development Goals" (RTCOV 2021), pages 392-397
ISBN: 978-989-758-617-0
Copyright
c
2023 by SCITEPRESS Science and Technology Publications, Lda. All rights reserved
national legal order. Moreover, in our opinion, the
systematic method cannot be bypassed when it comes
to comparing the system of international law and the
system of internal law of a particular state. This
allows us to define a systematic method as a system-
forming one within the framework of our
methodology.
3 PROBLEMS OF THE TERM
"STATE"
The term "state" in classical jurisprudence was used
without any qualifications, with the exception of the
terms "police state" and "rule of law". If we follow
Lundstedt's argumentation, then these terms can be
regarded as double fictions: "state" - "police" and
"state" - "law".
The reality of the "police" is not difficult to
imagine and even prove. However, according to
Lundstedt's logic, the entire materiality of the
"police" easily evaporates if we perceive the "state"
as a reified term, that is, as something that exists side
by side and independently of "workers and
employers." How to imagine a (state) police without
workers and employers?
The reality of "right" is much more difficult to
imagine. The first that comes to mind is the legislative
body, which consists of deputies who themselves are
not "rights", but create the so-called black letter law.
The problem here is that legislators can, in principle,
pass illegal laws. According to the well-known
formula of Gustav Radbruch, they can do “legislative
wrong, that is, anti-law": "Where there is no even
striving for justice, where equality, which is the core
of justice, is deliberately rejected in development of
positive law, there the law is not only a "wrong right",
but rather, it is generally devoid of legal nature"
(Radbruch, 1946).
Finally, a third perspective on combining the
terms “law” and “state” is offered by Oliver Wendell
Holmes, Jr., according to which “law is just a
prophecy about what the courts will actually do”
(Holmes, 2009). From the point of view of Holmes,
and then of American legal realists, the sphere of law
actually and practically coincides with what judges
do. Wherein, it is necessary to distinguish between
the performative (in principle, ritual) acts of judges
within the framework of the theory of neutral state
power, on the one hand, and the motivational (socio-
cultural, psychological and even emotional) triggers
of their behavior, on the other one. It is the latter that
form the judge law, for example, in the spirit of
Hofeld (Hohfeld, 1919).
A universal definition of the state was offered by
the famous Austro-German state scholar Georg
Jellinek. It is still replicated in textbooks on public
law in Germany as a three-pillar theory of the state
(Germ. "Drei-Elemententheorie") (Jellinek, 1929).
According to this theory, the state is a political
community that combines three characteristics
(elements): territory, population and an organized
administrative apparatus (bureaucracy). All three
signs shall be present in order for the state to take
place legally.
Less well known is the definition formulated by
the famous French administrativeist Maurice Oriou,
who defines the state in terms of combining public
and private law, namely as the imposition of "a public
thing on a private thing" (fr. L'etat est la superposition
d’une chose publique à la chose privée) (Hauriou,
1930).
“This does not mean at all that (political - auth.)
community is more than individuals. However, this
means that, to a significant extent, the benefit
intended for individuals cannot be provided otherwise
than through the community, perhaps because in this
way the distribution of benefits and advantages is
carried out more egalitarian than if it were left to the
arbitrariness of private initiatives. So, let us note that
the community of a public thing (res publica - author)
is nothing more than a tool for better servicing a
private thing by means of managing it"(Hauriou,
1930). Hence, Maurice Oriou draws the following
conclusion: if from a public thing (public need) there
is a danger for private things (personal interests), then
it lies in the excessive intensification of the
administrative and tax regime (Hauriou, 1930).
4 ADMINISTRATIVE STATE IN
THE GRIP OF
NEOLIBERALISM
In Europe in the eighteenth and early nineteenth
centuries, almost all states were "police" in the sense
that "law and order" were almost the only function of
European monarchies. However, from the second half
of the 19th century, the political elite, with the
exception of the conservative monarchists, began to
persistently distance the term "state" from the term
"police state". Ideologically, the concept of "state"
has become an abbreviated formula for the term "rule
of law" (Bähr, 1864; Gneist, 1872; Gumplowicz,
1881).
Neoliberal Administrative State, Digitalization and Pandemic
393
Nevertheless, one cannot draw a sharp line between
them, there is no reason to believe that the rule of law
in the spirit of liberal individualism of the second half
of the 19th century has ceased to be a police state in
the spirit of the "night watchman state", another thing
is important: in the liberal worldview of the second
half of the 19th century, the rule of law clearly
associated with the parliamentary regime (the
executive branch is derived from the parliament and
is accountable to it) and the (many) party system
(political parties as public organizations are called
upon to “supervise” the state, forcing it to publicity,
transparency, and etc.).
Undoubtedly, the rule of law in the era of classical
liberalism by itself could not evolve into a "social
state" without a "white revolution" (in the spirit of
Otto von Bismarck) or a "red revolution" (in the spirit
of V.I. Ulyanov-Lenin). However, a mystery remains:
how did the currently dominant matrix called the
"neoliberal state" manage to digest almost all the
previous ones — primarily primitive populism and
elitist individualism?
It shall be noted that “the most basic feature of
neoliberalism is the systematic use of state power to
inculcate the imperatives of financial markets in
domestic politics to the accompaniment of
(politicians –author). "Globalization" at the
international level" (Saad-Filho and Johnston, 2005).
As mentioned above, neoliberalism has absorbed
almost all the previous -isms. However, in this
ideological "compote" the paradoxical combination
of individualism and totalitarianism is striking.
The first genetic line of neoliberalism goes back
to the beloved brainchild of Adam Smith "homo
oeconomicus". This "ideal type" of a rational
individual is aimed at his/her own benefit and always
subordinates his/her behavior to calculation and
personal benefit. The second genetic line goes back to
the practice of real socialism, which, however, was
not always limited to verbal populism and harsh
totalitarianism.
5 ADMINISTRATIVE DIGITAL
STATE IN THE CONTEXT OF A
PANDEMIC
The COVID-19 pandemic marked, in our opinion, a
change in the political and legal paradigm of Western
civilization: we are talking about the actual
transformation of a constitutional state with its
characteristic liberal democratic regime into a
“neoliberal empire”. Its regime can be characterized
as predominantly administrative and, in tendency,
totalitarian.
We have already mentioned the specifics of the
administrative regime above. Here a double question
arises: how does the administrative regime “degrade
into a totalitarian one, or is it about the transformation
of the classical liberal-democratic regime, which in
an incredible way is gradually acquiring a
“totalitarian face”, in which, in our opinion, two
aspects are clearly visible: one of them is closely
related to the digitalization process, the second – to
the socio-political challenges of the 2019 pandemic.
Digitalization processes can be considered, at
least, in two ways: firstly, as an internal process of
optimization of the administrative (managerial) state,
aimed at rationalizing the bureaucratic workflow,
and, secondly, as an external process of optimizing
the welfare state, aimed at removing barriers and
intermediate links between administrative apparatus
and ordinary citizens. Therefore, the term "electronic
government" was initially ambivalent: on the one
hand, this term could mean a document flow system
within the administrative apparatus, on the other
hand, it could mean an external system of interaction
and feedback with the population.
Professor Ulrich Jan Schroeder notes four
digitalization trends that characterize the relationship
between the state administration and its citizens
(Schröder, 2019). First, we are talking about the
increase in power (Machtgewinn), which the state
acquires in relation to citizens and private firms. This
trend symbolizes the transition of the ruling class
from the regime of "electronic government", where it
is difficult to deny the component of the "welfare
state" in the service of citizens, to the regime of the
"neoliberal administrative empire", the goal of which
is to achieve the most complete transparency of each
individual for the "sovereign's eye".
Secondly, we are talking about the danger of loss
of control (Kontrollverlust) of the state over
management processes: algorithms for the
digitalization of state activities, as a rule, are not
transparent to bureaucrats. The positive effect of this
opacity is that the subjective factor (corruption,
arbitrary discretion, and etc.) is minimized, but there
is also a negative effect: the increased vulnerability of
the state to all kinds of hacker attacks poses a
particular danger.
Third, the digitalization of such democratic
institutions as elections, freedom of opinion, and etc.
is able to transform the constitutional and legal
essence of the liberal-democratic regime. First of all,
we are talking about the institution of subjective
public rights (die subjektiv-öffentlichen Rechte),
RTCOV 2021 - II International Scientific and Practical Conference " COVID-19: Implementation of the Sustainable Development Goals
(RTCOV )
394
which since the time of Georg Jellinek has been the
core of the constitutional regime of the civilized states
of the West (Jellinek, 1919).
Fourth, the special dependence (die Besonderheit
erhöhter Bindungen) on the state of those private
firms that use digitalization or are open to it is
increasing. Here Professor Ulrich Jan Schroeder notes
a tendency that works in a counter-direction towards
the already discussed third tendency. In other words,
the digitalization of the private sector expands and
details the scope of its obligations in the context of
the interaction of public and private law (Schröder,
2019).
Let's onsider all four trends in the focus of the
current pandemic:
1. The digitalization of the "covid database" - in a
trend - each citizen symbolizes, at least,
"administrative co-residence" or even the merging of
"electronic government" in terms of a welfare state,
on the one hand, and a neoliberal administrative state"
aimed at total control, on the other one.
2. The digitalization of the "covid database"
carries a significant risk of losing administrative
control not only over the way this data is stored, but
also over the protection of personal data. In other
words, the risks extend not only to the possibility of
unexplained disappearance of these data, but also to
the possibility of their change as a result of an
unexpected program failure, imperfection or
unpredictability of the behavior of algorithms.
3. The digitalization of the "covid database"
certainly changes the mode of functioning of
subjective public rights. In a trend, the logic of the
neoliberal administrative empire may lead to the fact
that not only "antivaxerism" (which means an active
anti-vaccination position), but also non-compliance
with the "vaccination schedule" can be regarded as
disloyal and antisocial behavior subject to
administrative punishment.
4. Wherein, the digitalization of medical
institutions in terms of rationalization and
optimization of individual "covid databases" shall
objectively contribute to an increase in the
responsibility and professionalism of medical
workers. First of all, we are talking about the strict
observance of antiquarian standards in the system of
relations "doctor - patient".
6 STUDY RESULTS
The cross-cutting core of our study is the opposition
"objective-subjective" in the specifics of legal
science, which, in principle, cannot abandon the
dichotomy "objective law - subjective law", although
it allows a change of places between "objective" and
"subjective" in it. For example, this approach is
characteristic of the institutional theory of law by
Maurice Oriou: “So, the subjective is supported by
our conscious wills, and the objective - by our
subconscious ideas. Having said this, we have
touched upon ... the strife (la querella) between
subjective law and objective law" (Hauriou, 1968).
As you can see, according to Oriou, for a civilized
legal order, the system of subjective rights is the goal
and, at the same time, the content, and objective law,
including positive law, is an instrument and, at the
same time, a sphere of ensuring subjective rights.
Within the framework of the topic we have
declared, this means the inevitable interaction of
“objective and subjective” in three angles: (1) within
the framework of the topic “state”, (2) within the
framework of the topic “digitalization” and (3) within
the framework of the topic “pandemic”. Let us
summarize first in relation to (1) and (3). We are in
solidarity with M. Oriu that the state is an
instrumental concept. This does not necessarily mean
that the state is just a fiction, just a “word” that, within
the framework of the dominant “narrative”, performs
a purely ideological function in the spirit of
postmodernism (Foucault, 1975).
According to Oriou's institutional theory, the state
is social institutions (for example, a contract, money,
family, private enterprise), one way or another taken
under political control by the ruling elite. Only by
relying on these institutions the state power can
become more or less effective. The Achilles' heel and
- as Hannah Arendt put it - the "stupidity" of the
neoliberal political elite is that it deliberately ignores
these social institutions and tries to destroy them. This
is possible only through the destruction of human
civilization, together with all its "elites". Within the
framework of the neoliberal administrative empire
project, we see a classic example of solipsism, i.e.
complete ideological, but not actual "triumph" of the
subjective over the objective.
With regard to the topic of "pandemic", there is a
situation of ambiguous "parity" between the
subjective and objective perspectives on this problem.
On the one hand, discussions about the man-made
nature of this pandemic and the objective
expectations of some of its results on the part of all
carriers of neoliberal ideology, including in the
context of the controversial conspiracy theory of
elites, do not cease. On the other hand, only the most
inveterate "antivaxer" can insist on denying the
objective nature of the current pandemic.
Neoliberal Administrative State, Digitalization and Pandemic
395
Finally, “digitalization” in its purely functional
form brings us back to common sense, which is
“encoded” in the “objective-subjective” dichotomy.
Digitalization algorithms do not make analogous
assumptions like "a little more or less," or "which is
better: half empty or half full glass". If digitalization
algorithms minimize the human factor, then this also
applies to the future destinies of the project called
“neoliberal empire”.
7 RESULT DISCUSSION
The following conclusions can be drawn from the
administrative-legal concept of Maurice Oriou:
private-law relations, in principle, do not need
support from the "state authority": they arose
before the state, they can exist outside the
effective control of the state and, in principle,
can generally "work" in a competitive mode
with state structures (for example, the system
of hawala cross-border payments) (Korolev,
2016). "Therefore, private law can be imagined
without the state" (Hauriou, 1930).
the administrative state as a system of public
administration is primary, and the
constitutional state as an organization of
supreme power and as an institution of human
rights is secondary. In terms of the founder of
the German school of administrative law, Otto
Mayer, this conclusion sounds like this:
"Verfassungsrecht vergeht, Verwaltungsrecht
besteht" (German: "constitutional law will
pass, administrative law will remain") (Stor
and Schröder, 2010).
From the reasoning of Ulrich Jan Schroeder,
the following conclusions can be drawn:
Digitization, speaking metaphors, transforms
the image of a whole, indivisible, polysemantic
person in his/her natural analogue environment
into a certain digital code, into a certain number
of pieces (bits) of information about this
person. In this case, there is a digital
"diversification" of information about one and
the same individual. The digital person turns
into a "database", so his/her digital medical
record is in principle separable from his/her
digital tax card, digital educational card, digital
travel card, and etc.
In principle, each of these cards can be
“blocked”, made a priority, or, on the contrary,
irrelevant. In other words, from a “digital
person” it is possible to construct any
configuration from his/her “digital cards” and,
thereby, manipulate and even blackmail a real
(analog) person as a “reflection” of his/her
digital twin.
During the current pandemic, not even a
“digital medical record” is becoming a priority,
but its “covid heading”. This happens not only
for objective reasons, i.e. in order to curb the
pandemic.
The benefits for the neoliberal administrative state
are clear:
firstly, the entire spectrum of political
opposition in the context of a pandemic, for
objective reasons, is formalized under one
syncretic heading "antivaxers"; it is much
easier to keep under social control (no matter
how) a consolidated group, than many
heterogeneous groups and, especially, an
immense multitude of individuals with their
personal qualities and differences;
secondly, "antivaxers" actually oppose
themselves to the rest of the population, tired of
the pandemic, and, therefore, turn into a
convenient target for preventive or repressive
measures on the part of the neoliberal
administrative state;
thirdly, “antivaxerism” is becoming an
aggravating connotation in the future for those
who became “antivaxer” as an initial democrat,
Christian conservative, Islamic preacher, trade
union activist, and etc.; in other words,
“antivaxerism” becomes a kind of political
“shibboleth”, making this or that political
spectrum “asocial”;
therefore, a purely special mark in the "digital
passport" of an individual works in principle
the same way as the criminal history of one or
another individual when looking for work.
8 CONCLUSIONS
Since the last third of the last century, the world's
population has been subject to systematic pressure
from neoliberalism, they proclaimed the "end of
history" (Fukuyama, 2006) including the
"depoliticization" of public life, which is allegedly
governed by "economic laws" based on the principles
of competition and economic individualism.
In fact, neoliberalism has no scientific basis: the
"economic laws" proclaimed by the apologists of
neoliberalism are only a means of systematic
indoctrination of national elites and a tool for
manipulating the minds of the masses. The emphasis
is on, first, to deprive people of a sense of social and
RTCOV 2021 - II International Scientific and Practical Conference " COVID-19: Implementation of the Sustainable Development Goals
(RTCOV )
396
political solidarity, to convince people of the
"correctness" of neo-Darwinian individualism and
personal struggle for survival. Second, in order to
neutralize the political will of the individual, who is
no longer able not only to implement, but even to
understand one of the main aspects of human dignity:
"In the struggle you will acquire your right", which
Rudolf von Iering made the epigraph of his famous
brochure "Struggle for the Right" (Jhering, 1872).
Oddly enough, the objective process of
digitalization, with all its threats and risks, can
become the gravedigger of neoliberalism as the main
enemy of human civilization. However, objectively,
this result is unattainable without interaction with a
subjective, first of all, political and moral-
psychological factor.
ACKNOWLEDGMENT
The reported study was funded by Russian
Foundation for Basic Research (RFBR), project
number 18-29-16012.
REFERENCES
Korolev, S.V., 2016. Savigny's “People's Spirit” and
Iering's “Jurisprudence of Interests” on the Example of
the Hawala Informal Settlement System, Law and the
State in Their Correlation: Theoretical Legacy of the
Historical School of Law, pages 124-134.
Schmitt, K., 2000. Political Theology, Moscow: Kanon-
Press-C, Kuchkovo Pole, 336.
Arendt, H., 1976. The Origins of Totalitarianism [1948] –
San Diego, New York, London: Harcourt Brace and
Company, 577.
Jellinek, G., 1919. System der objektiven öffentlichen
Rechte. 2-te Aufl, Tübingen: Mohr- Siebeck, 378.
Jellinek, G., 1929. Allgemeine Staatsrechtslehre. 3. Aufl,
Berlin: Springer, 885.
Kelsen, H., 1992. Die reine Rechtslehre. 2te Aufl. [1960],
Wien: Österreichische Staatsdruckerei, 404.
Kovalik, D., 2017. The Plot to Scapegoat Russia: How the
CIA and the Deep State Have Conspired to Vilify Putin,
N.Y.: Skyhorse, 240.
Lyles, M.A., 2006. Call for Scientific Purity. Axel
Hägerström’s Critique of Legal Science, Stockholm:
Institutet för Rättshistorisk Forskning, 701.
Mundus, P.A., 2009. Real Mind. The Life and Worl of Axel
Hägerström, Dordrecht Heidelberg London New York:
Springer, 283.
Lundstedt, A.V., 1932. Die Unwissenschaftlichkeit der
Rechtswissenschaft. Bd. 1. Berlin-Grunewald.
Radbruch, G., 1946. Gesetzliches Unrecht und
übergesetzliches Recht, Süddeutsche Juristenzeitung,
pages 105-108.
Holmes, O.W., 2009. Jr. The Path of the Law [1897],
Auckland (N.Z.): The Floating Press, 42.
Hohfeld, W.N., 1919. Fundamental Legal Conceptions as
Applied in Judicial Reasoning and Other Essays.
Edited by W. W. Cook. New Haven, London: Oxford
University Press, 115.
Hauriou, M., 1930. Précis élémentaire de droit
constitionnel. 2me edition, Paris: Recueil Sirey, 346.
Hauriou, M., 1968. La teoria de la institucion y de la
fundacion. Traduccion del frances par A.E. Sampay,
Buenos Aires: Abeledo-Perrot, 76.
Bähr, O., 1864. Der Rechtsstaat, Cassel; Göttingen:
Wigand, 232.
Gneist, R., 1872. Der Rechtsstaat. Berlin: Springer, 214 pp.
Gumplowicz, L., 1881. Der Rechtsstaat und Sozialismus,
Innsbruck: Verlag der Wagner’schen Universitäts-
Buchhandlung, 575.
Saad-Filho, A., Johnston, D. (eds.), 2005. Neoliberalism. A
Critical Reader, London, Ann Arbor: Pluto, 277.
Schröder, U.J., 2019. Die Digitalisierung der Staatsgewalt
– Rechtswandel, rechtliche Grenzen und dogmatische
Desiderate. https://ulrich-jan-schroeder.de/2019/11/02/
die-digitalisierung-der-staatsgewalt-rechtswandel-
rechtliche-grenzen-und-dogmatische-desiderate-2/.
Foucault, M., 1975
. Surveiller et punir. Naissance de la
prison. Paris: Gallimard, 313.
Fukuyama, F., 2006. The End of History and the Last Man
[1992], N.Y.: Free Press, 464.
Jhering, R. der Kampf ums Recht, Wien: Verlag der G. J.,
1872. Manz’schen Buchhandlung, 109.
Storr, St., Schröder, R., 2010. Allgemeines
Verwaltungsrecht, Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 341.
Neoliberal Administrative State, Digitalization and Pandemic
397