FROM CYBORG TO CYBERPUNK
The Art of Living in the Cyberage
A. T. Nuyen
Department of Philosophy, National University of Singapore, 3 Arts Link, Singapore 117570
Keywords: Art of living, Bio-power, Cyberage, Cyberpunk, Cyborg, Foucault, Harraway, Heidegger, Leary.
Abstract: The World Wide Web, the Internet and other cyber technologies have changed the way we live and work. In
addition to such technologies, and interwoven with them, are biological technologies, such as those in the
areas of cloning and genetic engineering. Some of us welcome the technological age, some are hostile to it,
most are ambivalent, and hardly anyone approaches it with the Socratic question “How should one live?”
The context in which Socrates asks this question, in The Republic, is different, but in the context of modern
technology, electronic as well as biological, the significance of the question remains the same: Not a trifling
matter as Socrates puts it. Indeed, the new technologies have changed the way we conduct ourselves so
drastically, and the way we think about ourselves so fundamentally, that Socrates’ question must now be
asked with urgency. In what follows I offer some reflections on how one should live with the new
technologies, drawing on the works of Foucault, Heidegger, Leary and Haraway.
1 INTRODUCTION
Cyber technologies have changed the way we live
and work. In addition to such technologies, and
interwoven with them, are biological technologies,
such as those in the areas of cloning and genetic
engineering. Some of us welcome the technological
age, some are hostile to it, most are ambivalent, and
hardly anyone approaches it with the Socratic
question “How should one live?” The context in
which Socrates asks this question, in The Republic,
is different, but in the context of modern
technologies, electronic as well as biological, the
significance of the question remains the same: Not a
trifling matter as Socrates puts it. Indeed, the new
technologies have changed the way we conduct
ourselves so drastically, and the way we think about
ourselves so fundamentally, that Socrates’ question
must now be asked with urgency. In what follows I
offer some reflections on how one should live with
the new technologies.
2 THE ART OF LIVING
According to Foucault, the emancipation of the self
consists in efforts to construct oneself, “to promote
new forms of subjectivity” and “to build up what we
could be” (Foucault, 1982: 126). Using art as a
model, Foucault urges us to construct ourselves
aesthetically as a response to any kind of
domination. He calls on us to develop an “aesthetics
of existence” consisting of a set of “arts of
existence,” or “technologies of the self.” Foucault
defines the “arts of existence” as “those intentional
and voluntary actions by which men not only set
themselves rules of conduct, but also seek to
transform themselves, to change themselves in their
singular being, and to make their life into an oeuvre
that carries certain aesthetic values and meets certain
stylistic criteria” (Foucault 1986a: 10-11). The point
is later reinforced when Foucault calls for “the
cultivation of the self … in the form of a new
stylistics of existence,” for forming oneself “as an
ethical subject of his actions,” and giving oneself “a
purpose to his existence” (Foucault 1986b: 95).
The construction of the self is urged by Foucault
as a means to resist power in power relations. Power
occurs in complex strategic situations in a society
and is exercised by a free agent over another free
agent, thus linking free agents in a strategic
situation. Power relationships produce social
realities. They make a society possible. Furthermore,
it is trough them that we understand ourselves. How
power is exercised is a question of power politics. In
92
T. Nuyen A. (2007).
FROM CYBORG TO CYBERPUNK - The Art of Living in the Cyberage.
In Proceedings of the Third International Conference on Web Information Systems and Technologies - Society, e-Business and e-Government /
e-Learning, pages 92-96
DOI: 10.5220/0001267700920096
Copyright
c
SciTePress
his earlier works, Foucault focuses on a particular
kind of power politics, the exercise of power to
discipline and to punish. What is characteristic of
power in this phase of its history is that it is the
power of degrading life, and ultimately of taking life
away, or conferring death. Also, it is a power
exercised on agents individually. But as pointed out
in Foucault’s later works, since the Enlightenment,
there has been a shift in the nature of power politics.
Governments have increasingly exercised their
power to give life, or to make life better, over the
population as a whole rather than individually.
Foucault calls this new form of power “bio-power.”
It is the power to “make live” (faire vivre) in
contrast to the old power of “giving death.” Bio-
power has given rise to bio-politics with a different
set of power “dispositifs,” or apparatuses of control.
However, the effect on free agents remains the same
as before. Thus, while bio-power takes on life as its
object, exercised so as to “make live,” it is still a
disciplinary power in political terms.
While Foucault was prescient about bio-power,
given the fact that we are now living in what one
scientist calls “the age of biological control”
(Wilmut 1999), he did not see the full ramifications
of the power exercised in cyberspace, of “electronic
control.” The experience in certain countries may
lead us to believe that the latter power is diffused,
rested in the hand of “Net citizens” and so does not
pose the same control problem as bio-power. To be
sure, new power relationships have emerged –
individuals have been shamed, condemned, made
famous or notorious, simply because their conduct
has been recorded and posted on the Net – but they
seem to be benign, even egalitarian, or democratic.
However, this is to ignore the fact that given the
technical complexities and the costs of supporting
the electronic technologies, the electronic control,
exercised through the control of technological
apparatuses, such as networks and servers, is really
concentrated in the hands of a few. In addition,
electronic control has been fused with biological
control, resulting in a whole new set of power
dispositifs and a whole new set of control
mechanisms. Think of the proliferation of data bases
containing medical and biological information and
the technological devices that have emerged or are
being planned in the name of fighting a “war on
terror” or controlling pandemics. Seeing these
ramifications, Foucault would regard electronic
power as an extension of bio-power.
Given the combination of electronic and
biological control, given what might be called
bio/techno power, the question is whether there is
room for the construction of the self, whether there
can be an effective resistance to the new power
relations. Many commentators have gone so far as
saying that there is not enough freedom left for the
task of self-construction, that resistance to bio-
technological power is useless. For instance, Hardt
and Negri contend that a global “Empire” is
emerging, wielding an omnipotent and all pervasive
bio/techno power that “regulates social life from its
interior” (Hardt and Negri, 2000: 23). This is an
empire consisting of gigantic multi-national
corporations, many of which operate in the areas of
bio-technology, logistics and security, and all are
capable of controlling the life of the population. Just
as pessimistic is Giorgio Agamben. Unlike Hardt
and Negri, who locate the new power relations in the
business empire of multi-national corporations,
Agamben locates it in the alliance between the State
and the experts, the latter consisting of the technical
experts (doctors and engineers) and the legal and
moral experts (jurists and priests) (Agamben, 1998).
In support of Agamben and Hardt and Negri, in the
case of the Internet, one might cite the “alliance,” or
the co-operation, between the Chinese Government
and corporations such as Google and Yahoo! in
controlling Net communication. Indeed, there have
been cases in which political activists have been
identified and subsequently incarcerated by the
government with the help of such corporations. The
modern power of “giving life” has not really
displaced the old power of “taking life.”
Clearly, in the age of bio-techno control,
Foucault’s call for an art of living is all the more
urgent. How do the new power relationships affect
the free agent, who, as a subject, must defend the
subject’s freedom in establishing relationships, with
oneself and others, in all strategic situations, which
is for Foucault the “very stuff of ethics”?
Foucault’s answer is not to free oneself of
power relationships but rather to engage in power
relationships in a particular way, i.e. aesthetically.
That means, in turn, to engage in resistance. There is
little evidence to show that Foucault would go as far
as Agamben and Hardt and Negri. For Foucault,
resistance is certainly neither impossible nor useless,
even in the most disciplinarian state. It is true that in
the new bio/techno-political environment, resistance
is practically much more difficult. This is so because
Hardt and Negri are certainly right about the
growing power of multi-national corporations, and
Agamben about the growing alliance between the
State and the experts. How then is one to live, as a
free agent, in the age of bio-technological control?
FROM CYBORG TO CYBERPUNK - The Art of Living in the Cyberage
93
How does one make resistance into an art of living,
or an ethical response to the Socratic question?
3 LIVING IN CYBERSPACE
One way of living in the age of bio-technological
control is to live stoically in the face of modern
technology, i.e. avoiding anything technological.
Another is to go over to modern technology in a
manner that effectively means giving up all
resistance. However, both of these ways would be
inauthentic, to borrow a term from Heidegger. In a
well known essay, Heidegger argues that we must
not succumb to “a stultified compulsion to push on
blindly with technology or, what comes to the same
thing, to rebel helplessly against it and curse it as the
work of the devil” (Heidegger, 1977: 25-6). Rather,
we need to confront technology decisively and
reflect constantly on its essence. To accomplish this,
we have to wrench ourselves away from the dazzling
effects of technology and turn to something else.
That something else, this realm, is art, or the art of
living. This is the meeting between Heidegger and
Foucault.
Returning to Foucault, the art of living must
exhibit resistance, and in the electronic age, it is
resistance to bio-technological control. However, it
has to be much more than resistance. To resist is to
say no, and to resist bio/techno-power is to say no to
certain forms of conduct encouraged by the new
technology: “You have to say no as a decisive form
of resistance” (Foucault 1997: 168). But to say no is
only to make half a step. Without going further, it is
an inauthentic moving of “rebelling helplessly”
against technology that Heidegger speaks against.
The other half is to create. Foucault argues that
“resistance is not solely a negation but a creative
process,” that to “create and recreate … is to resist”
(ibid.). Against bio/techno power, it is to create a life
that is not dictated by technology. For Foucault,
such a life will have to be unique, a product of art.
Free agents can remain free by creating for
themselves forms of life that “affirm themselves; not
merely affirm themselves in their identity, but affirm
themselves insofar as they are a creative force”
(ibid.). What forms of life? I will now discuss two
suggestions.
Many commentators on technology have offered
arguments for resistance consistent with Foucault’s
call for the construction of the self, and have given
examples that manifest the art of living in the face of
bio-technological control, an art that manifests
creative resistance. For Timothy Leary, the
cyberpunk embodies such art (Leary 1996: 355-
363). Leary reminds us that the word “cyber” comes
from the Greek word “kybernetes,” meaning one
who steers a boat or a vessel, a pilot. A
“cyberperson” is “one who pilots his/her own life,
[who] continually searches for theories, models,
paradigms, metaphors, images, icons that help chart
and define realities that we inhabit” (Leary, 1996:
355). The word “punk” refers to a rebellious youth
who engages in what appear to be anti-social
practices, such as wearing outrageous hairdos, body-
piercing, playing or listening to “punk rock” etc. For
leary, in the age of bio-technological control, the
cyberpunk is someone who offers resistance in a
creative way: “Cyberpunks use all available data
input to think for themselves …” (ibid.). They are
like the “heroic legends,” the “strong, stubborn,
creative individuals who explore some future
frontier, collect and bring back new information, and
offer to guide the human gene pool to the next
stage” (ibid.). Leary distinguishes two types of
people living in the cyber society, the “good person”
who is a cyberpunk and “the problem person … who
automatically obeys, who never questions authority,
who acts to protect his/her official status, who
placates and politics rather than thinks
independently” (Leary, 1996: 356). We may add to
these two types the Heideggerian inauthentic person
who either avoids anything technological or goes
over to it in a slavish way.
For Leary, while the term “cyberpunk” seems
risky, it is a perfect term to describe the good
cyberperson, one who understands cyberpolitics and
offers up a creative, self-constructing resistance. He
reminds us that the Latin translation of the Greek
word “kubernetes” comes out as “gubernetes,”
formed fromgubernare,” which does mean to steer,
but also to govern, to direct, to regulate, etc., i.e. to
control (Leary, 1996: 357). On the other side of the
coin, the direct Latin word for “to steer” is “
stare,”
the past participle of which “produces ‘status,’
‘state,’ ‘institute,’ ‘statue,’ ‘static,’ ‘statistics,’
‘prostitute,’ ‘restitute,’ ‘constitute’” (ibid.), all of
which refer to the state of being controlled. The two
faces of the word “cyber,” freedom (to steer one’s
life) and control, are reflected in the history of the
Internet, originally a tool of control set up by the
U.S. military, now vulnerable to cyberpunks. Using
the word “cyberpunk” is a deliberate act of
“liberating the term [“cyber”], teasing it free from
serfdom to represent the autopoetic, self-directed
principle of organization that arises in the universe
in many systems of widely varying sizes, in people,
societies, and atoms” (Leary, 1996: 358). It
WEBIST 2007 - International Conference on Web Information Systems and Technologies
94
represents a return to the “Hellenic concept of the
individual navigating his/her own course, … an
island of humanism in a raging sea of totalitarian
empires” (Leary, 1996: 359). The cyberpunk, then,
is the hero we need in the struggle against the Hardt-
Negri Emoire, the grand Agambenian alliance of the
State and the experts. He or she is a person who
embraces and personalizes information technology
in the process of constructing his or her self.
While Leary sees the cyberpunk as “an island of
humanism in a raging sea of totalitarian empires,”
Donna Haraway goes further in advocating what
might be called a post-human form of life, that of a
cyborg, a hybrid being that combines human
elements with non-human ones (haraway, 1996).
Haraway has in mind a human-machine organism,
but recent advances in stem cell research, in which
human-animal chimeras are created, may be seen as
ushering in the post-humanistic age populated with
human-animal-machine cyborgs. With the
technology in our hands, we can break free from
biological constraints and create, or recreate,
humans from the physical ground up. The
cyberpunks will no longer have things done to their
bodies, or wear them as accessories: they can have
them genetically engineered into them. They will in
turn perform one of the tasks that Leary has
envisioned for them, namely “guid[ing] the human
gene pool to the next stage.” As is well known,
Foucault himself went from the structuralist phase
characterized by anti-humanistic views (declaring
the “death of man” in one of his structuralist works),
to the post-structuralist phase characterized by the
talk of self-constructing resistance. The kind of post-
humanism that Haraway speaks of seems to be the
polical end-point of the Foucauldian trajectory.
In a language that is distinctly Foucauldian,
Haraway gives her own account of power,
domination and resistance in the cyberage. For
Haraway, the bio-technological age has a new
“informatics of domination” (Haraway, 1996: 384)
and a new “microelectronic and biotechnological
politics” (Haraway, 1996: 385). In the new politics,
“[C]ontrol strategies will be formulated in terms of
rates, costs of constraints, degrees of freedom”
(Haraway, 1996: 386). We have already seen that
“robotics and related technologies put men out of
work in ‘developed’ countries and exacerbate failure
to generate male jobs in third-world ‘development’
and as the automated office becomes the rule even in
labor-surplus countries, the feminization of work
intensifies” (Haraway, 1996: 390). A new economic
underclass has emerged, the new subjects of modern
bio-technological control. Microelectronics has
worsened the situation insofar as the controlling
agencies, the “states, multinational corporations,
military power, welfare-state apparatuses, satellite
systems, political processes…” etc. all “depend
intimately upon electronics” (Haraway, 1996: 387).
As if agreeing with Agamben and Hardt and Negri,
Haraway presents a catalogue of the controlling
effects of the new technologies, presenting a bleak
“image of the informatics of domination” (Haraway,
1996: 392): “a massive intensification of insecurity
and cultural impoverishment, with common failure
of subsistence network for the most vulnerable”
(Haraway, 1996: 394). The Socratic question is now
desparately relevant and Foucault’s call for the
resistance in our art of living is now desparately
urgent.
Given the rather bleak picture painted by
Haraway, is resistance to bio-technological control
possible and if so how is it effected? Indeed,
believing that the time has come to go beyond even
Foucault, Haraway claims that the answer lies in the
cyborg: “The cyborg is not subject to Foucault’s
biopolitics; the cyborg simulates politics, a much
more potent field of operations. Discursive
constructions are no joke” (Haraway, 1996: 386).
The cyborg thus resists by means of discursive
constructions. What does this entail? If I understand
Haraway correctly, we can say that in the post-
humanistic age, distinctions, particularly binary
ones, such as human-animal, human-machine,
animal-machine, natural-artificial, will be crossed,
or transcended. They will no longer serve to restrict
or circumscribe creativity. Instead, the crossing of
boundaries allows infinite flexibility in the
construction of the self. For Haraway, binary
distinctions, or dichotomies, are the tools of
domination, and the cyborg, embodying the crossing
of binaries, takes advantage of the blurring of
distinctions in its resistance to domination. The
cyborg takes advantage of the fact that “[H]igh-tech
culture challenges … dualisms in intriguing ways”
(Haraway, 1996: 399): “Cyborg politics is the
struggle for language and the struggle against perfect
communication, against the one code that translates
all meaning perfectly, … [It] insist(s) on noise and
advocate(s) pollution, rejoicing in the illegitimate
fusion of animal and machine” (Haraway, 1996:
398). In cyborg politics, the “machine is us”
(Haraway, 1996: 402). Insofar as we are
“responsible for boundaries,” machines “do not
dominate or threaten us … [for] we are they”
(Haraway, 1996: 402). Haraway will no doubt agree
that the “they” includes animals and animal-human-
machine hybrids.
FROM CYBORG TO CYBERPUNK - The Art of Living in the Cyberage
95
I have discussed two responses to Foucault’s
challenge to resist bio-technological control, to
construct the self creatively so as to live well in the
bio-electronic age, or the cyberage. Whether they are
the right answers to the Socratic question remains to
be seen. What we can say is that it is certainly not
Socratic wisdom to “put up with or evade” bio-
electronic technologies, to borrow Heidegger’s
words. It is not to give in to the empires of bio-
technological multi-national corporations, or the
grand alliances of states and experts.
It may be said, however, that there is something
missing in the suggestions made by Leary and
Haraway. What limits are there on the creativity of
cyborgs and cyberpunks? It seems that what is
missing is the ethical dimension. Foucault himself
does not lose sight of this. His art of living consists
in the building of relationships with others, which
are for Foucault the “very stuff [matière] of ethics”
(Foucault, 1986a: 95). The new technologies can
greatly assist a free subject in living an ethical form
of life. The Foucauldian subject, who resists and
constructs itself in resisting, is also an “ethical
subject.” The image of the cyberpunk, or the cyborg,
is Foucauldian only if it is the image of an ethical
cyberpunk, or an ethical cyborg. Haraway may be
right in saying that “discursive constructions are no
joke,” but unethical discursive constructions most
probably are. Foucault would certainly say that
constructing an ethics for the cyberpunk, or the
cyborg, to live by is “the very stuff of ethics” in the
bio-electronic age. To do so is beyond the scope of
this paper, although I have argued elsewhere that
Lyotard’s postmodern ethics of just gaming, the
imperative of which is to let games proliferate,
seems to be eminently suitable (Nuyen, 2004).
Where to go from here? What games are to be
created? What would be the content of the art of
living? The answers to these questions can only, at
best, be gestured at. The idea of specifying content,
of constructing a “model” for living, contradicts the
idea of living creatively. Foucault himself speaks
merely of “certain stylistic criteria” without
specifying them. Here again, art serves as an
analogy: there is good art and bad art, the former
satisfies “certain stylistic criteria.” However, to
specify the criteria that an artist must satisfy is
almost certain to produce bad art. The cyberpunk
creates his/her own criteria; the cyborg transcends
existing ones. Yet, there have to be criteria, without
which what we have is randomness, not art. Criteria,
but they will have to be what Kant calls
“regulative.” They cannot be what Kant calls
“determinant.” The art of living is regulated, but not
determined by anything.
REFERENCES
Agamben, G., 1998. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and
Bare Life, trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen. Stanford
University Press. Stanford, California.
Foucault, M., 1982. The Subject and Power. In Michel
Foucault: Beyond Structualism and Hermeneutics.
Trans. Herbert L. Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow.
Harvester Press. Brighton, Sussex.
Foucault, M., 1986a. The Use of Pleasure. Trans. Robert
Hurley. Vintage Books. New York.
Foucault, M., 1986b. The Care of the Self. Trans. Robert
Hurley. Pantheon. New York.
Foucault, M., 1997. Sex, Power and the Politics of
Identity. In Ethics, Subjectivity and Truth. Ed. Paul
Rabinow. Trans. Robert Hurley. New Press. New
York.
Hardt, M., and Negri, A., 2000. Empire. Harvard
University Press. Cambridge, Mass.
Haraway, D., 1996. A Manifesto for Cyborgs: Science,
Technology, and Socialist Femenism in the 1980s. In
CyberReader. Ed. Victor I. Vitanza. Simon and
Schuster. Needham Heights, Mass.
Heidegger, M., 1877. The Question Concerning
Technology. In The Question Concerning Technology
and Other Essays. Trans. William Lovitt. Harper and
Row. New York.
Leary, T., 1996. The Cyberpunk: The Individual as Reality
Pilot. In CyberReader. Ed. Victor I. Vitanza. Simon
and Schuster. Needham Heights, Mass.
Nuyen, A.T., 2004. Lyotard’s Postmodern Ethics and
Information Technology. Ethics and Information
Technology. Vol.6, pp.185-191.
Wilmut, I., 1999. The Age of Biological Control. In The
Genetic Revolution. Ed. Justine Burley. Oxford
University Press. Oxford.
WEBIST 2007 - International Conference on Web Information Systems and Technologies
96